• About
  • Contact
  • Staff
  • Home
  • Blog
  • Forum
  • Podcasts
  • Book Reviews
  • Liberty Classics

February 6, 2019|Children, Consent, Gordon Tullock, Holly Brewer, James Buchanan, John Rawls

Children, Consent, and Liberalism

by James R. Rogers|6 Comments

Image: Konstantin Christian / Shutterstock.com

 

Liberalism, both classical and modern, has always had difficulty fitting children into its consent-based theories. In modern consent theories, “consent” is a theoretical fiction, one used as a proxy for “reasonableness.” Thus John Rawls’ veil of ignorance behind which deracinated humans choose principles of justice. Or Buchanan and Tullock’s original position in which individuals choose a constitution uncertain of what their endowments will be in the post-constitution world.

Earlier social contract theorists used the state of nature in a similar fashion. They used the idea not so much as a description of some sort of real original position, but as a useful fiction to help themselves and their readers think through reasonable political institutions, meaning institutions they would identify as optimal due to abstract considerations rather than choose them because those institutions would protect their already vested interests. It’s unclear whether “consent” ever referred to something real.

But when the American Declaration of Independence affirms that the “just powers” of government derive from the “consent of the governed,” it’s not clear, however the phrase be understood, that there is not supposed to be empirically observable consent of one form or another. Thus, the actual nature of consent, and who can—and cannot—consent, and what is consented to, becomes a pivotal issue in the American political tradition.

In her book, By Birth or Consent: Children, Law, and the Anglo-American Revolution in Authority, historian Holly Brewer provides an absolutely fascinating account of the change in Anglo-American relationships—legal, political, ecclesial, and social—from sounding in status to sounding in consent. She describes this transition through the lens of historically evolving views of the ability of children to consent in these different spheres. Brewer does nothing less than trace the evolution of the central postulate of liberalism from theory to practice.

The scope of this legal and social transformation is breathtaking. Brewer provides evidence of child “consent” throughout the Anglo-American world of the 16th and 17th centuries. Children themselves could contract, and so legally oblige themselves, to marriage as young as seven:

Four-year-olds could make wills to give away their goods and chattels. Children of any age could bind themselves into apprenticeships. Eight-year-olds could be hanged for arson or any other felony. Teenagers were routinely elected to Parliament.

And the list of adult responsibilities that children could undertake goes on.

The issue was not limited to law and government. Brewer devotes a chapter to a heated debate in Protestant ecclesiology, the argument over infant baptism. (The alternative to infant baptism was limiting baptism to individuals who have reached some ill-defined age of accountability.) It wasn’t a simple dualism, however. The debate even roiled the circles of those who continued to practice infant baptism but could not agree on its import: What did baptism mean for an infant? Which infants could be baptized—those whose parents were believers, or could believing grandparents qualify an infant for baptism? What obligations, if any, did undergoing the rite as an infant imply when the child matured?

Brewer shows the interconnection of republican political theory with changing conceptions of church membership and ecclesiology, and she demonstrates that “consent” was the byword connecting debates in both civil and ecclesiastical spheres.

Understandably given the distant in time of the documents with which she works, Brewer concedes her “study does not show prevalence, which is nearly impossible to discern.” Rather, “it sketches the big picture—establishing that assumptions were very different from our own, and that we, whether social or political historians, should not take our own norms for granted.” Getting a glimpse into a mindset alien to today’s liberalism is the treat this volume offers. Brewer’s work underscores just how fundamentally liberal all Americans are today, whether they identify as liberal or conservative, religious or not. “Consent” is the god to whom all Americans genuflect today.

Fetching as well is the thread Brewer recurs to through her book tracing ironic implications of the reorientation of so much of life around the notion of mature consent. Not least, she points out children were systematically infantilized by the decisional shift from the authority of status to the authority of consent. The move to “consent” took choice away from children, whether they were capable of exercising mature consent or not. The result was that their lives were placed firmly in the hands of others. To be sure, the reader can ask whether many children were truly exercising their own agency when, say, contracting a marriage at age eight, or whether parents or guardians were already exercising real agency, binding children to future courses of action under the guise of the children’s decision.

Moreover, by reorienting the authority for making a binding decision from status to mature consent, Brewer argues the debate over children carried metaphorical resonances into other relationships. By analogizing women and slaves to “children” in their ostensible inability to provide mature consent, the changing legal status of children’s decisions provided a rhetorical framework used to justify deprivation of choice to infantilized adults.

I do have a quibble or two, as well as thoughts on the implications of Brewer’s argument for liberalism today. I’ll take those up in a subsequent post or two.

James R. Rogers

James Rogers is associate professor of political science at Texas A&M University, and is a fellow with the Institute for Science, Technology and Public Policy at the Bush School of Government and Public Service. He also served as editor of the Journal of Theoretical Politics from 2006 through 2013.

About the Author

Will the Right to Bear Arms Become a “Constitutional Orphan”?
Contracts and Solemnities in Adam Smith’s Sacred Anthropology

Recent Popular Posts

  • Popular
  • Today Week Month All
  • Hell Is Truth Realized Too Late: Russia and the Legacy of World War I February 21, 2019
  • State Versus National Citizenship in Our New Federalism February 22, 2019
  • The Campus Mob Comes for the Presumption of Innocence February 19, 2019
  • Obama and Trump: At What Point Has a President Forfeited the Public Trust? February 19, 2019
  • Right Populism, Left Populism, and Constitutional Constraints February 22, 2019
Ajax spinner

Related Posts

Related

Comments

  1. gabe says

    February 6, 2019 at 11:53 am

    ““Consent” is the god to whom all Americans genuflect today.”

    Indeed, this is clearly true; so much so that recently some “consent-addled” feminist professor encouraged us to seek the “consent” of infants PRIOR to changing their diapers.

    Not to be outdone, an Ivy league academic later asserted that adult-child sexual encounters are to be accepted provided the young child consents. It was unclear whether this devotee of Smith and Locke was a member of NAMBLA.

    Well, I no longer consent to having to hear this idiocy from the elite, highly *trained* minds of the university.

    Reply
    • gabe says

      February 7, 2019 at 12:05 pm

      But wait, screams the pitchman, “There is more”:

      https://www.foxnews.com/world/indian-man-to-sue-his-parents-for-giving-birth-to-him-without-his-consent-wants-to-be-paid-for-his-life

      wherein we learn that the “consent” fetish has now reached its inevitable terminus – suing your parents because you were conceived by then WITHOUT your consent.

      Hmm! will no one raise the issue in the obverse? – suing your parent for terminating you without your consent.

      What sheer and utter stupidity and narcissism.

      Reply
  2. Karen Renfro says

    February 6, 2019 at 2:34 pm

    It is hard to know where to start. The idea that true Liberty cannot exist unless children have the same legal rights as adults does not come from the wisdom of our ancestors, but from foolish people who wish to vindicate their conscience.

    Well, as I understand Liberty–and by that I mean the sacred, inalienable right given by God to every individual human being in equal measure–it is not simply freedom to do as you please without regard to the consequences. The American Revolution was not based on the foolish ideas of French philosophes, but on a long and winding tradition I like to call “Judeo-Christian Natural Law”. Because, interestingly, there is such a thing.

    The Founders did not define Liberty as freedom from any kind of control. To them, it meant “freedom from external control”. Their definition of Liberty is “Freedom and Independence”, independence meaning “self-control, self-government, and/or self-reliance & self-restraint”.

    And if you think you are looking at the Golden Rule, it is no accident. John Adams defined Liberty as “a power to do as we would be done by”. This Rule is considered the summation of the Laws of God and Nature. His whole generation shared that view. Maybe there were individuals here and there who did not agree, but if they wanted to be accepted in society they had to act as if they did.

    That is because Liberty is more about creating a society where, if individuals execercise the virtues that define it, they will automatically be protecting the rights and dignity of others, and if they reciprocate, everyone’s rights will be secured. No government can guarantee that level of Liberty.

    George Bernard Shaw once said, “Liberty means responsibility. That is why most men dread it.” The libertarian view of Liberty no longer bears any resemblance to the Founders’ views. Children need guidance and training to learn how to exercise self-reliance and self-restraint, otherwise they will lead very unhappy lives and so will everyone around them.

    Children need protection from sexual predators, a class of criminal that specializes in gaining a child’s trust before persuading them to become their victim. The fact that adults can be victimized this way, too, shows how fragile a person’s self-respect can be. The fact that children can become predators at a young age shows how evil this practice is.

    I am very unhappy that the subject of child consent has been brought up in a forum that is supposed to be devoted to Liberty, a gift of God that is meant to uplift us, not degrade us. Liberty is not about having sex with whomever you wish whenever you wish, regardles of the consequences.

    If you want to understand the meaning of the Declaration of Independence, go back and read the Self-Evident Truths again, and this time ask yourself why they said Liberty cannot exist in the absence of morality.

    Reply
    • gabe says

      February 7, 2019 at 10:54 am

      Yes, Liberty / freedom is best or most fully exercised in its self-restraint AND that is clearly what the Founders believed and intended.

      Also, see Richard Reinsch’s essay on Solzhenitsyn and his critique of Western conceptions of liberty.

      Reply
  3. EK says

    February 7, 2019 at 12:03 pm

    I scanned the Amazon preview of Brewer’s book a bit and was not impressed. She seems to focus on England and Virginia and bases her argument mostly on anecdotes or sui generis kinds of cases that made the Year Books.

    As Brewer’s focus seems to be consent and the rights of children under the patriarchy it may be that Brewer is front-running something that NAMBLA might find attractive.

    Brewer is correct that the idea that the political order should rest on the consent of the governed is closely associated with the English Reformation of the 17th C. But, it is not clear that Brewer recognizes how limited the franchise was in 17th C. England. The estimates I’ve read place the number of actually franchised 40 shilling free holders at less than 5% of the population. Then again, enfranchisement and voting do not seem to be the subject of her book.

    The issue of “the consent of the governed” as opposed to the long established “consent of Parliament” seems to have entered English politics in October 1647 at St Mary’s Church in Putney when the Army Council of the New Model Army was debating what to do about a Parliament dominated by Presbyterians that wanted to keep the monarchy, disband the the army and enforce Presbyterian conformity on England.

    The Soviet historians had no trouble recognizing Army Council as a revolutionary republican workers and soldiers soviet. It was made up 50-50% split of “agitators” from the ranks and officers. All were freely elected by their peers. The opinions represented in the Council ranged from a narrowly confined monarch in a constitutional monarchy to a democratic republic with no kings, no bishops, no lords and no established religion.

    At the debate, Col. Thomas Rainborowe, soon to be John Winthrop’s brother-in-law, spoke for the republican faction and argued that “least hee” in England could not be justly bound to a government he had not consented to. In the context of the debate, I think it likely Rainborowe was arguing that the rank and file in New Model Army and their Leveller allies in London had to consent to whatever government eventually emerged from the revolution. On the other side, Gen. Henry Ireton, Cromwell’s son-in-law, argued for “property,” which included not only land and personal property but also one’s inherited civil status and all its customary perquisites.

    Back to Brewer: In New England in the 1630s the age of consent for legal documents and for voting was 21 and remained so for over 300 years, although males age 16 and over were automatically part of the unorganized militia. Orphans and indigent children under 21 could not be apprenticed or indentured by themselves or by relatives who were not their parents without court approval.

    Reply

Trackbacks

  1. Individualism, Consent, and Community says:
    February 12, 2019 at 5:52 am

    […] I discussed earlier, Historian Holly Brewer’s book, By Birth or Consent: Children, Law, & the Anglo-American […]

    Reply

Leave a Reply Cancel reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

Book Reviews

A Compelling and Compassionate Book about Epilepsy

by Theodore Dalrymple

Our knowledge of the human brain is limited, but neuroscientist Suzanne O’Sullivan’s observation of her patients yields astute insights.

Read More

Andrew Roberts Takes the Measure of the “Populist” Aristocrat, Churchill

by Joao Carlos Espada

Yes, there is something new to be learned about Winston Churchill, and it’s in the new 1,105-page biography by Andrew Roberts.

Read More

Liberty Classics

Paul Heyne and the Trouble with Economists

by Nikolai G. Wenzel

Economics is often a morality-free zone, and Paul Heyne shows why this is a mistake.

Read More

Bringing Natural Law to the Nations

by Samuel Gregg

If sovereign states ordered their domestic affairs in accordance with principles of natural law, the international sphere would benefit greatly.

Read More

Podcasts

Born-Again Paganism: A Conversation with Steven Smith

A discussion with Steven D. Smith

Steven Smith talks with Richard Reinsch about his provocative thesis that a modern form of paganism is becoming public orthodoxy.

Read More

"Slouching Towards Mar-a-Lago:" A Conversation with Andrew Bacevich

A discussion with Andrew J. Bacevich

Andrew Bacevich discusses his new book Twilight of the American Century

Read More

Bureaucracy, Regulation, and the Unmanly Contempt for the Constitution

A discussion with John Marini

John Marini unmasks the century-long effort to undermine the Constitution’s distribution of power.

Read More

Beautiful Losers in American Politics: A Conversation with Nicole Mellow

A discussion with Nicole Mellow

Nicole Mellow on the beautiful losers in American politics who have redefined the country.

Read More

Recent Posts

  • State Versus National Citizenship in Our New Federalism

    We are fast abandoning the fundamental jurisprudence of our law that legislatures make general rules and courts apply them to specific circumstances.
    by Thomas Ascik

  • Right Populism, Left Populism, and Constitutional Constraints

    A good constitution thus can cabin the damage that popular movements may do, while still permitting them to shake up complacent elites.
    by John O. McGinnis

  • Hell Is Truth Realized Too Late: Russia and the Legacy of World War I

    Had the costs of war and revolution been understood, Russia might have avoided much of what it suffered over the 20th century.
    by William Anthony Hay

  • Did New York City Really Lose Out in Amazon Deal?

    Perhaps we should be with the socialists on this one: NYC did not lose much in net by Amazon’s pullout.
    by James R. Rogers

  • A Corrupt Republic? Hamilton, Madison, and the Rise of Oligarchy

    Jay Cost asks his readers to reconsider the ways that corruption all too easily flows from the federal government, in every era.
    by Tony Williams

Blogroll

  • Acton PowerBlog
  • Cafe Hayek
  • Cato@Liberty
  • Claremont
  • Congress Shall Make No Law
  • EconLog
  • Fed Soc Blog
  • First Things
  • Hoover
  • ISI First Principles Journal
  • Legal Theory Blog
  • Marginal Revolution
  • Pacific Legal Liberty Blog
  • Point of Law
  • Power Line
  • Professor Bainbridge
  • Ricochet
  • Right Reason
  • Spengler
  • The American
  • The Beacon Blog
  • The Foundry
  • The Originalism Blog
  • The Public Discourse
  • University Bookman
  • Via Meadia
  • Volokh

Archives

  • All Posts & Publications
  • Book Reviews
  • Liberty Forum
  • Liberty Law Blog
  • Liberty Law Talk

About

Law & Liberty’s focus is on the classical liberal tradition of law and political thought and how it shapes a society of free and responsible persons. This site brings together serious debate, commentary, essays, book reviews, interviews, and educational material in a commitment to the first principles of law in a free society. Law & Liberty considers a range of foundational and contemporary legal issues, legal philosophy, and pedagogy.

  • Home
  • About
  • Staff
  • Contact
  • Archive

© 2019 Liberty Fund, Inc.

This site uses local and third-party cookies to analyze traffic. If you want to know more, click here. By closing this banner or clicking any link in this page, you agree with this practice.Accept Read More
Subscribe
Get Law and Liberty's latest content delivered to you daily
  • This field is for validation purposes and should be left unchanged.
Close